Chapter Two
al Baqarah (The Cow)
286 verses – Medina
In the name of Allâh, the
Beneficent, the Merciful. Alif Lâm mîm (1) . This Book, there is no
doubt in it, (is) a guidance to those who guard (against evil) (2),
Those who believe in the unseen and keep up the prayer and spend (benevolently)
out of what We have given them (3), And who believe in that which has been
sent down to thee and that which was sent down before thee and they are sure of
the hereafter (4). These are on a guidance from their Lord and these it is that
shall be the successful ones (5).
GENERAL COMMENT
This chapter was revealed
piecemeal; therefore, it does not have a single theme. However a major part of
it shows a general objective: It emphasizes that a man cannot be a true servant
of Allâh unless he believes in all that was revealed to the apostles of
Allâh without making any difference between revelation and revelation, or
between apostle and apostle; accordingly, it admonishes and condemns the disbelievers,
the hypocrites and the people of the book because they differed about the
religion of Allâh and differentiated between His apostles; thereafter it
ordains various important laws, like change of the direction to which the
Muslims were to turn for their prayers, regulations of hajj, inheritance
and fasting and so on.
COMMENTARY
QUR’ĀN: Alif lâm
mîm: God willing, we shall describe in the 42nd chapter some things
related to the "letter-symbols" that come at the beginning of
some chapters. Also, the meaning of the guidance of the Qur’ân and of its
being a book will be explained later on.
QUR’ĀN: This Book, there
is no doubt in it, (is) a guidance to those who guard (against evil), those
who believe in the unseen: Those who guard against evil, or in other words,
the pious ones, are the very people who believe. Piety, or guarding oneself
against evil, is not a special virtue of any particular group of the believers.
It is not like doing good, being humble before God or purity of intention,
which are counted as various grades of the faith. Piety, on the other hand, is
a comprehensive virtue that runs through all the ranks of the true faith. It is
for this reason that Allâh has not reserved this adjective for any
particular group of the believers.
The characteristics of piety,
enumerated in these four verses, are five: Believing in the unseen, keeping up
prayers, spending benevolently out of what Allâh has given, believing in
what Allâh has revealed to His apostles, and being sure of the hereafter.
The pious ones acquire these spiritual qualities by a guidance from Allâh,
as Allâh tells us in the next verse: "These are on a guidance from
their Lord ". They became pious and guarded themselves against evil
because Allâh had guided them to it. When they got that quality, the
Qur’ân became a guidance for them: "This Book . . . (is) a guidance
to those who guard against evil". It clearly shows that there are two
guidances, one before they became pious, the other after it. The first guidance
made them pious; and thereupon Allâh raised their status by the guidance
of His Book.
The contrast is thus made clear
between the pious ones on one hand and the disbelievers and the hypocrites (who
are admonished in the next fifteen verses) on the other. The later two groups
are surrounded by two strayings and two blindnesses. Their first straying
causes their unbelief and hypocrisy, and the second one (which comes after
their unbelief and hypocrisy) confirms their first error and strengthens it.
Look at what Allâh says about the disbelievers: Allâh has set a
seal upon their hearts and upon their hearing; and there is a covering over
their eyes (2:7) . Sealing their hearts has been ascribed to Allâh, but
the covering over their eyes was put by the disbelievers themselves. Likewise,
Allâh says about the hypocrites: There is a disease in their hearts, so
Allâh added to their disease (2:10). The first disease is attributed
to the hypocrites themselves, and the second one to Allâh. The same
reality has been explained in many verses. For example: He causes many to
err by it and many He leads aright by it! But He does not cause to err by it (any)
except the transgressors (2:26) ; . . . but when they turned aside,
Allâh made their hearts turn aside (61:5).
In short, the pious ones are
surrounded by two guidances, as the disbelievers and hypocrites fall between
two errors. The second guidance is by the Qur’ân; therefore, the first one
must have been before the Qur’ân. They must have been guided by a healthy
and unimpaired psychology. If a man's nature is faultless and flawless, it
cannot fail to see that it is dependent on some thing above it. Also, it
realizes that every other thing, which it may perceive, imagine or understand,
depends likewise or, a thing outside the chain of dependent and needy things.
Thus, it comes to believe that there must be a Being, unseen and imperceptible
through the senses, who is the beginning and end of every other thing. It also sees
that the said Essential Being does not neglect even the smallest detail when it
comes to creative perfection of His creatures. This makes him realize that the
said Creator cannot leave the man to wander aimlessly hither and thither in his
life; that He must have provided for him a guidance to lead him aright in his
actions and morals. By this healthy reasoning, the man acquires the belief in
One God, in the institution of prophethood and in the Day of Resurrection. In
this way, his faith in the fundamentals of religion becomes complete. That
faith leads him to show his servitude before his Lord, and to use all that is
in his power - wealth, prestige, knowledge, power, and any other
excellence - to keep this faith alive and to convey it to others. Thus we
come to the prayer and benevolent spending. The five virtues enumerated in
these verses are such that a healthy nature unfailingly leads the man to them.
Once a man reaches this stage, Allâh bestows on him His another grace,
that is, the guidance by the Qur’ân.
The above-mentioned five
qualities - correct belief and correct deeds - fall between two
guidances, a preceding one and a following one. This second guidance is based
on the first one. This fact has been described in the following verses : Allâh
confirms those who believe with the sure word in this world's life and in the
hereafter (14:27). O you who believe! fear Allâh and believe in His
apostle. He will give you two portions of His mercy, and make for you a light
with which you will walk . . . (57:28). O you who believe! if you help
Allâh, He will help you and make firm your feet (47:7) . And
Allâh does not guide the unjust people (61:7) . . . . and
Allâh does not guide the transgressing people (61:5).The same is the
case with error and straying of the disbelievers and hypocrites, as will be
seen later on.
The above verses give an
indication that man has another life, hidden behind this one. It is by that
life that he lives in this world as well as after death and at resurrection.
Allâh says: Is he who was dead then We raised him to life and
made for him a light by which he walks among the people, like him whose
likeness is that of one in utter darkness whence he cannot come forth . . . (6:122).
We shall explain it, God willing, later on.
Those who believe in the unseen" "al- Īmân”
( = faith, to
believe) is consolidation of belief in heart. It is derived from al-amn
( =
safety, to feel safe). The believer, by his belief and faith, gains safety from
doubts. (Needless to say that doubt is like a poison to the faith.)
It has already been explained
that faith has many grades. Sometimes one is certain of the object of faith;
and this certainty has its effects; at other times the certainty increases and
includes some concomitants of the said object; and at times it increases to include
all the related matters of the object of faith. Naturally, the belief, thus, is
of various grades and so are the believers. "al-Ghayb" ( = the unseen) is opposite
of "the perceived". It is used for Allâh, and His great signs,
including the revelation, which is referred to in the clause, "And who
believe in that which has been sent down to thee and that which was sent down
before thee". Also, it includes the hereafter. But in these verses, the
beliefs in the revelation and in the hereafter have been separately mentioned.
Therefore, "the unseen" must have been used for Allâh only. In
this way the belief in the three fundamentals of religion becomes complete.
The Qur’ân emphasizes that
man should not confine his knowledge and belief to only the perception; it
exhorts him to follow healthy reasoning and rational understanding.
QUR’ĀN: and they are sure
of the hereafter: Instead of only believing in the hereafter, they are sure
of it. There is an indication here that one cannot be pious, cannot guard
himself against evil, until he is really certain of the hereafter - a
certainty that does not let him forget it even for a short time. A man believes
in a matter, yet sometimes forgets some of its demands and then commits
something contrary. But if he believes in, and is sure of, the day when he
shall have to give account of all that he has done -big or small -
he will not do anything against the divine law, will not commit any sin.
Allâh says: . . . and do not follow desire, lest it should lead you
astray from the path of Allâh; (as for) those who go astray from
the path of Allâh, for them surely is a severe punishment because they
forgot the day of reckoning (38:26). Clearly it is because of forgetting
the Day of Reckoning that man goes astray. It follows that if one remembers it
and is sure of it, he will surely guard himself against evil, will become
pious.
QUR’ĀN : These are on
guidance from their Lord and these it is that shall be the successful ones: Guidance
is always from Allâh, it is not ascribed to anyone else except in a
metaphorical way.
Allâh describes His guidance
in these words: Therefore (for) whomsoever Allâh intends that He
would guide him aright, He expands his breast for Islam . . . (6 :125) . If
one's breast is expanded, he will be free from every tightness and
niggardliness. And Allâh says that: . . . whoever is preserved
from the niggardliness of his soul, these it is that are the successful ones (59:9).
Therefore, He says in this verse about those who are on His guidance that
"they shall be the successful ones".
TRADITIONS
as-Sâdiq (a.s.) said
about the words of Allâh: Those who believe in the unseen: "Those
who believe in the rising of al- Qâ'im
(
= one who stands, i.e., al-Mahdi, the twelfth Imam - a. s. ) that
it is truth." (Ma’âni '1-akhbâr )
The author says: This
explanation is given in other traditions also; and it is based on the
"flow" of the Qur’ân.
According to at-Tafsîr
of al-`Ayyashi, as-Sâdiq (a.s.) said about the words of
Allâh: and spend (benevolently) out of what We have given them, that
it means: the knowledge We have given them.
In Ma`âni 'l-akhbâr,
the same Imam has explained it in these words: "And they spread the
knowledge We have given them and they recite what We have taught them of the
Qur’ân.
The author says: Both
traditions explain the "spending" in a wider sense that includes
spending the wealth as well as using other bounties of Allâh in His cause;
the explanation given by us earlier is based on this exegesis.
A PHILOSOPHICAL DISCUSSION
Should we rely on rational
concepts, in addition to the things perceptible through the senses? It is a
subject of great controversy among the western scholars of the later days. All
Muslim philosophers as well as most of the western ones of ancient times
believed that we can rely on the rational as well as the sensual perceptions.
They were rather of the opinion that an academic premises does not look at a
tangible and sensual factor as such. But most of the modern scholars,
especially the scientists, hold that nothing can be relied upon except what one
perceives through the five senses. Their proof is as follows:
Pure rational proofs often go
wrong. There is no test or experiment, perceptible through the senses, to
verify those rational proofs or their premises.
Sensual perceptions are free from
this defect; when we perceive a thing through a sense, we verify it through
repeated tests and experiments; this testing continues till we are sure of the
characteristics or properties of the object of test.
Therefore, sensual perception is
free from doubt, while rational proof is not.
But this argument has many flaws:
First: All the above-mentioned
premises are rational; they cannot be perceived by any of the five senses. In
other words, these scholars are using rational premises, to prove that rational
premises cannot be relied upon! What a paradox! If they succeed in proving
their view-point through these premises, their very success would prove
them wrong.
Second: Sensual perception
is not less prone to error and mistake than rational proof. A cursory glance at
the books dealing with the optics and other such subjects is enough to show
how many errors are made by sight, hearing and other senses. If rational proof
is unreliable because of its possible mistakes, sensual perception also should
be discarded for the same reason.
Third: No doubt, there
should be a way to distinguish the right perception from the wrong. But it is
not the "repeated testing", per se, that creates that
distinction in our mind. Rather, it becomes one of the premises of a rational
proof which in turn provides that distinction. When we discover a property of
an object, and the property remains the same through repeated tests, a rational
proof, on the following lines, is offered by our thinking power. If this
property were not this thing's own property, it would not be found in it so
unfailingly; But it is always found in it without fail; Therefore, it is its
own property. It is now obvious that sensual perception too depends on rational
premises to finalize its findings.
Fourth: Let us admit that
practically every sensual perception is supported by test. But is that test
verified by another test? If yes, then the same question will arise about this
later one. Obviously, it cannot go on ad infinitum; there must come at
the end a test whose verification depends not on a visible test but on the
above-mentioned rational proof. It means that one cannot rely on sensual
perception without relying on rational concepts.
Fifth: The five senses
cannot perceive absolute and major issues; they know only the particular and
minor things. Knowledge depends on absolute issues, which cannot be tested in
a laboratory nor can they be grasped by the five senses. A professor of anatomy
operates upon, or dissects, a number of living or dead human bodies - it
does not matter how large or small that number is. He finds that each of the
bodies - which he has opened - has a heart, a liver and the like.
And after looking at those particular cases, he feels bold enough to teach an
absolute proposition that all men have a heart and a liver. The question is:
Has he seen inside "all" the human beings? If only that much can be
relied upon which is perceived by the five senses, how can any absolute
proposition of any branch of science be accepted as true?
The fact is that sensual
perception and rational concept both have their place in the field of
knowledge; both are complementary to each other. By rationality and
understanding, we mean that faculty which is the source of the above examples
of absolute principles. Everyone knows that man has such a faculty. How can a
faculty created by Allâh (or as they say, by nature) be always in wrong?
How can it always fail in the function entrusted to it by the Creator? The
Creator never entrusts any work to an agent until He creates a connecting link
between them.
So far as mistakes in rational
and sensual faculties are concerned, the reader should look for it in related
subjects like logic etc.
ANOTHER PHILOSOPHICAL DISCUSSION
Man in his early childhood
perceives the objects around him; he knows them without knowing that he knows,
that is, without being aware that he has, or is using, a faculty called
knowledge or cognition. This continues until a time comes when he finds himself
doubting or presuming a thing. Then he realizes that before that he was using
"knowledge" in his life affairs. He also gradually comes to
understand that his perception or concepts are sometimes wrong, that error
cannot be in the materials that he perceives - because those material
things are facts and facts cannot be non-facts, that is, cannot be wrong.
Therefore, the error must be in his perception. When there is no error in
perception, it is knowledge - a perception that leaves no room for
opposite ideas.
By these stages, he becomes aware
of the basic principle that positive and negative are mutually exclusive and
totally exhaustive; they are contradictories, they cannot both be present nor
can both be absent. This fundamental truth is the foundation-stone of
every self-evident or theoretical proposition. (Even if one doubts this
statement, he intuitively knows that this "doubt" cannot be present
with its negative, with its "nondoubt".)
Man relies on knowledge in every
academic theory and practical function. Even when he feels doubtful about a
matter, he identifies that doubt by knowing that it is a doubt. The same
applies when he does not know, or only presumes, or merely imagines a thing, he
identifies it by the knowledge that it is ignorance, presumption or
imagination.
But in ancient Greece, there
arose a group, the Sophists, who denied existence of knowledge. They showed
doubt in every thing, even in their own selves, even in that doubt. The
Sceptics of later days are almost their successors. They deny knowledge of
every thing outside their own selves and their own minds. Their
"arguments" run as follows:
First: The most potent
knowledge (that comes through the five senses) is often wrong and in error.
Then how can one be sure of the knowledge obtained through other sources? How
can we rely, in this background, on any knowledge or proposition outside our
own selves?
Second: When we wish to
comprehend any outside object, what we get is merely its knowledge; we do not
grasp the object itself. Then, how can it be possible to grasp any object?
Reply to the First Argument:
First: This argument
negates and annihilates itself. If no proposition can be relied upon, how can
one rely on the propositions and premises used in this argument?
Second: To say that a
source of knowledge is "often" wrong, is to admit that it is also
correct many times. Then how can it be rejected totally?
Third: We have never said
that our knowledge is always correct. The Sophists and the Sceptics affirm that
no knowledge is correct. To refute this universal negative proposition, a
particular affirmative proposition is sufficient. That is, we have only to
prove that some knowledge is correct; and we have done so in the second reply.
Reply to the Second Argument: The issue in dispute is
knowledge, which means to unveil an object. The Sceptics admit that when they
try to comprehend an object, they get its knowledge. Their only complaint is
that they do not grasp the object itself. But nobody has ever claimed that
knowledge means grasping the object itself; our only claim is that knowledge unveils
some of the realities of its object, that is, of the thing so known.
Moreover, the Sceptic refutes his
own views practically in every movement and at every moment. He claims that he
does not know anything outside his own self, outside his own mind. But when he
is hungry or thirsty, he moves to the food or water; when he sees a wall
falling down, he runs away from it. But he does not try to get food when he
just thinks about hunger, and does not run away when he just thinks about a
falling wall. It means that he does not act on the pictures in his mind -
which he claims are the real things, and acts on that feeling or perception
which comes to him from outside - which, according to him, does not have
any reality and should not be relied upon!
There is another objection
against existence of knowledge. They deny existence of established knowledge;
and have laid the foundation of today's natural sciences on this rejection. Their
reasoning is as follows:
Every single atom in this world
is in constant movement; every single thing is continuously moving towards
perfection or deterioration. In other words, what a thing was at a given
instant, is not the same in the next. Understanding and perception is a
function of brain. Therefore, it is a material property of a material compound.
Naturally, this process too is governed by the laws of change and development.
It means that all functions of brain, including knowledge, are constantly
changing and developing. It is, therefore, wrong to say that there is any such
thing as established knowledge. Whatever knowledge there is has only relative
permanence - some propositions last longer than others. And it is this
impermanent conception that is called knowledge.
Reply: This argument is
based on the presumption that knowledge is not non-material and abstract;
that it is a physical thing. But this supposition is neither self-evident
nor proved. Knowledge is certainly non-material and abstract. It is not a
physical and material thing, because the attributes and properties of matter
are not found in it:
1. All material things are
divisible; knowledge, per se, is not divisible.
2. Material things depend on
space and time; knowledge, per se, is independent of space and time. An
event happens in a certain place and time, but we may comprehend it in any
place and at any time without any adverse effect on its comprehension.
3. Material things are admittedly
governed by the law of general movement and constant change. But knowledge, per
se, does not change. Knowledge, as knowledge, is incompatible with change,
as one may understand after a little meditation.
4. Suppose that knowledge, per
se, is subject to constant change like matter and material things. Then one
thing or event could not be comprehended with the same details, in exactly the
same way, at two different times. Nor could a past event be remembered
correctly later on. Because, as the materialists have said, "what a
(material) thing was at a given instant is not the same in the next".
These comparisons show that
knowledge, as knowledge, is not a material or physical thing. It must be told
here that we are not talking about the physical actions and reactions which an
organ of a sense or the brain has to undergo in the process of acquiring
knowledge. That action and reaction is a process, or a tool, of knowledge, it
is not the knowledge itself.
For more detailed discussion of
this subject one should study the philosophical works.