There have been other methods of thought in the
Islamic world, at variance with the illuminationist and peripatetic methods, that have
played genuine and basic roles in the development of Islamic culture. Two such methods are
'irfan (gnosis) and kalam (scholastic theology).
Neither the 'urafa' nor the muralallimin have regarded
themselves as followers of the philosophers, whether illuminationists or peripatetics.
They have taken stands against the philosophers and clashed with them. These clashes have
had an appreciable effect on the fate of Islamic philosophy. Irfan and kalam have
both motivated Islamic philosophy through conflict and clashes and opened up new horizons
for philosophy.
Four Islamic Approaches
Many of the questions Islamic philosophy addresses were first addressed by the mutakallimin
or the 'urafa; although they express themselves in a way different from that of
the philosophers. Islam comprehends four methods of thought, and Islamic thinkers are of
any of four sons. I am discussing methods of thought having a philosophical character in
the most general sense, that is, constituting an ontology and a cosmology.
I am treating the universals of philosophy, and not the methods of
thought of jurisprudence, exegesis, tradition, letters, politics, or ethics, which are
another matter entirely. Each of these methods has taken on a special character under the
influence of Islamic teachings and differs from its counterparts outside the Islamic
sphere. The particular spirit of Islamic culture governs each.
One method is the deductive method of peripatetic philosophy. It has
numerous adherents in history. Most Islamic philosophers, including Al-Kindi, Farabi,
Avicenna, Khwaia Nasir ad-Din Tusi, Mir Damad, Ibn Rushd of Andalusia, Ibn Baja of
Andalusia, and Ibn as-Sa'igh of Andalusia, have followed this method. The perfect exemplar
of this school is Avicenna. Such philosophical works of his as the Kitab ash-Shifa' (The
book of healing [the so called Sufficientia]), Isharat va Tanbihat (Allusions
and admonitions), Najat (Deliverance), Danishnama-yi Ala'i (The book of
knowledge, dedicated to 'Ala ad-Dawla), Mabda' va Ma 'ad (The source and the
destination), Ta'liqat-i Mubahathat (Annotations to the discussions), and 'Uyun
al-Hikma (Wellsprings of wisdom) are all works of peripateticism. This method relies
exclusively on rational deduction and demonstration.
A second method is the illuminationist method. This has fewer adherents
than the first method. It was revived by Shihab ad-Din Suhravardi and followed by Quth
ad-Din Shirazi, Shahrazuri, and a number of others. Suhravardi is considered the perfect
exemplar of this school. He wrote numerous books) including the Hikmar al-lshraq (Wisdom
of illumination), Talvihar (Intimations), Mutarahat (Conversations), Muqavamat
(Oppositions), and Hayakil anNur (Temples of light). The best known of them is
the Hikmat al-Ishraq; only this work is wholly devoted to the illuminationist
method. Suhravardi has written some treatises in Persian, among them Avaz-i Par-i Jabra
'ii (The song of Gabriel's wing) and Aql-i Surith (The red intelligence).
The illuminationist method rests on rational deduction and
demonstration and on endeavour and purification of the soul. According to this method, one
cannot discover the underlying realities of the universe through rational deduction and
demonstration alone.
The wayfaring method of 'irfan, or Sufism, is the third method.
It relies exclusively on a purification of the soul based on a concept of making one's way
to God and drawing near to the Truth. This way is said to culminate in the attainment of
Reality. The method of 'irfan places no confidence at all in rational deduction.
The 'urafa' say that the deductionists stand on wooden legs. According to the
method of irfan, the goal is not just to uncover reality, but to reach it.
The method of 'irfan has numerous adherents, some of whom have
grown famous in the Islamk world, including Bayazid Histami, Hallal, Shibli, Junayd of
Baghdad, Dhu'n-Nun Misri, Abu Sa'id-i Abi'l-Khayr, Khwaja 'Abdullah Ansari, Abu Talib
Makki, Abu Nasr Sarraj, Abu'l-Oasim Qushayri, Muhyi 'd-Din Ibn 'Arabi of Andalusia, Ibn
Faridh of Egypt, and Mawlana Rumi. The perfect exemplar of Islamic irfan, who
codified it as a science and had a compelling influence on all who followed him, is Muhyi
'd-Din Ibn 'Arabi.
The wayfaring method of 'irfan has one feature in common with
the illuminadonist method and two features at variance with it. Their shared feature is
reliance on reform, refinement, and purification of the soul. The distinguishing features
of each areas follows:
The 'arif wholly rejects deduction; the illuminationist upholds
it and uses thought and purification to aid each other. The illuminationist, like any
other philosopher, seeks to discover reality; the arif seeks to attain it.
Fourth is the deductive method of kalam. Like the peripatetic,
the mutakatlimin rely on rational deduction, but with two differences. First, the
principles on which the mutakallimin base their reasoning are different from those
on which the philosophers base theirs. The most important convention used by the mutakallimin,
especially by the Mu'tazilites, is that of beauty and ugliness.
However, they differ among themselves as to the meaning of this
convention: the Mu'tazilites regard the concept of beauty and ugliness as rational, but
the Ash'arites regard it as canonical. The Mu'tazilites have derived a series of
principles and formulae from this principle, such as the formula of grace and the
incumbency of the optimal (wujub-i aslah) upon God Most High.
The philosophers, however, regard the principle of beauty and ugliness
as a nominal and human principle, like the pragmatic premises and intelligibles propounded
in logic, which are useful only in polemics, not in demonstration. Accordingly, the
philosophers call kalam "polemical wisdom," as opposed to
"demonstrational wisdom."
Second, the mutakallimin, as opposed to the philosophers, regard
themselves as committed, committed to the defence of the bounds of Islam. Philosophical
discussion is free; that is, the philosopher has not the predetermined object of defending
a particular belief, The mutakallim does have such an object. The method of kalam
is subdivided into three methods: the Mu'tazilite, the Ash'arite, and the Shi'ite.
Mu'tazilites are numerous in history. There are Abu'l Hudhayl 'Allaf,
Nazzam, Jahiz, Abu 'Ubayda, and Mu'ammar ibn Muthanna, all of whom lived in the second or
third centuries of the Hijra. Qazi 'Abd al-Jabbar in the fourth century and Zamakhshari
around the turn of the fifth-sixth centuries also exemplify this school.
Shaykh Abu'l-Hasan Ash'ari (d. 330) perfectly exemplifies the Ash'arite
school. Qazi Abu Bakr Baqillani, Imam al-Haramayn Juvayni, Ghazali, and EaMir ad-Din Razi
all followed the Ash'ari method.
Shi'i mutakallimin are also numerous. Hisham ibn al-Hikam, a
companion of Imam Ja'far Sadiq (upon whom be peace) was a Shi'i mutakallim. The
Nawbakhti family, an Iranian Shi'i family, produced some outstanding mutakallims. Shaykh
Mufid and Sayyid Murtaza 'Alam al-Huda are also ranked among Shi'i mutakallimin. The
perfect exemplar of Shi'i kalam is Khwaja Nasir ad-Din Tusi. His Tajrid al-'Aqa
'id (Refinement of beliefs) is one of the most famous works of kalam. He was
also a philosopher and mathematician. After him, kalam took a wholly different
course and assumed a more philosophical character.
Among the Sunnis' works of kalam, the most famous is the Shark-i
Mavaqif (Elucidation of the stations), with text by Qazi 'Azud ad-Din Iji (a
contemporary of Hafiz, who praised him in his poetry) and annotations by Sharif Jurjani.
This work was deeply influenced by the Tajrid al- Aqa'id.
Sublime Wisdom
The four streams of thought continued in the Islamic world until they reached a point of
confluence called "sublime wisdom" (hikmat-i muta aliya). The
science of sublime wisdom was founded by Sadr al-Muta'allihin Shirazi (or Mulla Sadra) (d.
lO5O/l64o).'~ The term "sublime wisdom" occurs in Avicenna's Isharat, but
Avicenna's philosophy never became known by this name.
Mulla Sadra formally designated his philosophy sublime wisdom, and it
became so known. His school resembles Suhravardi's in method in seeking to combine
demonstration with mystic vision and direct witness, but it differs in its principles and
conclusions.
In Mulla Sadra's school, many of the points of disagreement between
peripateticism and illuminationism, between philosophy and 'irfan, or between
philosophy and kalam have been definitively resolved. Mulla Sadra's philosophy is
not a syncretism, however, but a unique philosophical system, that, although the various
Islamic methods of thought had an impact on its formation, one must regard as autonomous.
Mulla Sadra has written numerous works, among them the Asfar-arbaa
(The four journeys, or books), Ash-Shavahidar-Rububiya (Witnesses to lordship),
Mabda 'Va Maad (The source and the destination), Arshiya (On the
Empyrean), Masha'ir (The perceptual faculties), and Sharh-i Hidaya-yi Athir
ad-Din Abbari (An elucidation of Athir ad-Din Abhari's guidance).
Among Mulla Sadra's followers is Hajj Mulla Hadi Sabzavari
(1212/1798-1289/1878), author of the Kitab-i Manzuma (The rhymed book) and the Sharh-i
Manzuma (The elucidation of the rhymed book). A typical basic library for study of the
ancient sciences might consist of Sabzavari's Shark-i Manzuma, Mulla Sadra's Asfar,
Avicenna's Isharat and Shrja', and Suhravardi's Hikmat al-Ishraq.
Mulla Sadra organised the philosophical topics concerning the
intellectual and rational way in a manner paralleling the manner in which the 'urafa' had
propounded the way of the heart and spirit. The 'urafa hold that the wayfarer
accomplishes four journeys in carrying through the method of the arif:
The journey from creation to God. At this stage, the wayfarer attempts
to transcend nature as well as certain supernatural worlds in order to reach the Divine
Essence, leaving no veil between himself and God.
The journey by God in God. After the wayfarer attains proximate
knowledge of God, with His help the wayfarer journeys through His phases, perfections,
names, and attributes.
The journey from God to creation by God. In this journey, the wayfarer
returns to creation and rejoins people, but this return does not mean separation and
remoteness from the Divine Essence. Rather, the wayfarer sees the Divine Essence with all
things and in all things.
4. The journey in Creation by God. In this journey, the wayfarer
undertakes to guide the people and lead them to the Truth.
Mulla Sadra, considering that philosophical questions constitute a
"way," if a mental one, sorted them into four sets:
1. Topics that constitute a foundation or preliminary to the study oft
tauhid. These (the ordinary matter of philosophy) constitute our mental journey from
creation to God.
2. Topics of tauhid, theology, and divine attributes-The journey
by God in God.
3. Topics of the divine acts, the universal worlds of being-the
journey from God to creation by God.
4. Topics of the soul and the Destination (ma 'ad)-the
journey in creation by God.
The Asfar Arba 'a, which means the Four Journeys, is organised
on this basis. Mulla Sadra, who called his special philosophical system sublime wisdom,
referred to conventional philosophy, whether illuminationist or peripatetic, as common or
conventional philosophy.
Overview of Philosophies and Wisdoms
Philosophy and wisdom, in the widest sense, are variously classified from different
perspectives; but if we consider them from the standpoint of method, they fall under four
headings: deductive wisdom3 experiential wisdom, experimental wisdom, and
polemical wisdom.
Deductive wisdom rests on syllogism and demonstration. It has to do only with greater
and lesser, result and concomitant, contradictory and contrary, and the like. Experiential
wisdom pertains not only to deduction but to experience, inspiration, and illumination. It
takes its inspiration more from the heart than from the reason.
Experimental wisdom pertains neither to a priori reasoning and
deduction nor to the heart and its inspirations. It pertains to sense, trial, and
experiment. It takes the products of the sciences, the fruits of trial and experiment,
and, by interrelating them, welds them into wisdom and philosophy.
Polemical wisdom is deductive, but the premises for its deductions are
what logicians call common knowledge (mashhurar) and accepted facts (ma qbulat).
There are several kinds of premises to deduction, including first axioms (badihiyat)
and common knowledge. For instance, the idea that two things each equal to a third are
equal to each other, which is expressed in the phrase "the equal to the equal are
equal," and the idea that it is absurd for a proposition and its contradictory to
hold true at once are considered axiomatic. The idea that it is ugly to yawn in the
presence of others is considered common knowledge.
Deduction on the basis of axioms is called demonstration, and deduction
on the basis of common knowledge is considered an element of polemics. Therefore,
polemical wisdom means a wisdom that deduces global and universal ideas from common
knowledge.
The mutakallimin generally base their deductions on the beauty
or the ugliness of a thing, on rational beauty and ugliness, so to speak. The hukama' hold
that all beauty and ugliness relate to the sphere of human life; one cannot evaluate God,
the universe, and being by these criteria. Thus, the hukama' call kalam polemical
wisdom.
The hukama believe that the central principles of religion may
be better deduced from the premises of demonstration and in reliance on first axioms than
from the premises of common knowledge and polemics. In Islamic times, especially among the
Shi'a, philosophy, without departing from its mission of free inquiry and committing
itself in advance, gradually proved the best source of support for Islamic principles.
Accordingly, polemical wisdom, in the hands of such persons as Khwaja Nasir ad-Din Tusi,
gradually took on a demonstrational and illuminationistic character. Thus, kalam came
to be overshadowed by philosophy.
Although experimental wisdom is extraordinarily valuable, it has two
shortcomings. One is that its compass is confined to the experimental sciences, and the
experimental sciences are confined to what is sensible and palpable. Man's philosophical
needs extend beyond what is in the domain of sense experience. For instance, when we
discuss the possibility of a beginning of time, an end to space, or an origin for causes,
how are we to find what we seek in the laboratory or under the microscope? Thus,
experimental wisdom cannot satiate man's philosophical instinct and must elect silence on
basic philosophical questions.
The other shortcoming lies in the fact that the
value of experimental questions is rendered precarious by their confinement to and
dependence upon nature. Questions of experimental science have a time-bound value and may
grow obsolescent at any moment. A wisdom based on experiment is naturally precarious and
so does not meet a basic human need, the need for certainty. Certainty arises in questions
having mathematical abstraction or philosophical abstraction, and the meanings of
mathematical and philosophical abstractions can be clarified only by philosophy.
There remain deductive wisdom and experiential wisdom. The questions
discussed in the following sections should elucidate these two wisdoms and spell out
their value.
Problems in Philosophy
Being
Philosophical questions pivot on being. That which is to philosophy what the body is
to medicine, number is to mathematics, or quantify is to geometry is being qua being. It
is the subject of philosophy and all philosophical topics turn on it. In other words,
philosophy has for its subject existence.
Several kinds of questions turn on being. One is questions pertaining
to being, or existence, and its opposites in the two respective senses: nonbeing and
essence (mahiya). There is nothing but being in the objective world. Being has no
opposite outside the mind. But the conceptualising mind of man has formed two concepts
vis-a'-vis being or existence: nonbeing and essence (of course, essences). A range of
philosophical questions, especially in sublime wisdom, pertains to existence and essence,
and another range pertains to being and nonbeing.
A second group of questions pertains to divisions of being. Being in
its turn has divisions that are regarded as amounting to species of being; in other words,
being is divisible (for instance, into the objective and the subjective, the necessary and
the possible, the eternal and the created in time, the stable and the changing, the
singular and the plural, the potential and the act, and the substance and the accident).
Of course, these are the primary divisions of being, that is, the divisions that enter
into being by virtue of the fact that it is being.
To illustrate, divisions into black and white, large and small, equal
and unequal, odd and even, or long and short are divisions not in being qua being but in
being qua body or in being qua quantifiable. Corporeality in being
corporeality, or quantity in being quantity, admits of such division. However, division
into singular and plural, or division into necessary and possible, is division of being
qua being.
Close research has been done in philosophy as to the criteria for these
divisions, what distinguishes the divisions of being qua being from other
divisions. Some philosophers have regarded certain divisions as applying to body qua body
and thus falling outside the scope of first philosophy, but other philosophers for various
reasons have regarded these divisions as applying to being qua being and thus
falling under this same domain.
A third group of questions pertains to the universal laws governing
being, such as causality, the correspondence of cause and effect, the necessity governing
the system of cause and effect, and priority versus synchronism among the levels of being.
A fourth group of questions pertains to demonstration of the planes of
being or worlds of being. Being has particular planes or worlds. The hukama' of
Islam believe that there are four general worlds or four emergencies (nash'a):
1. The world of nature, or the nasut
2. The world of ideas, or the malakut
3. The world of [separate] intelligences, or the jabarut
4. The world of divinity, or the lahut
The world of nasut is the world of matter, motion, and
space-time. It is the world of nature and sense objects, this world. The world of
[Platonic] ideas [similitudes], or the malakut, is a world superior to
nature, having forms and dimensions, but lacking motion, time, and change.
The world Jabarut is the world of the [separate] intelligences or
the world of the [abstract] idea (ma'na), free of forms and images and thus
superior to the world of malakur. The world of lahut is the world of
divinity and unity.
A fifth group of questions pertains to the relations between the world
of nature and the worlds above it, the descent of being from lahut to nature, and
to the ascent from nature to the higher worlds. With special reference to man, these are
called questions of the destination (ma 'ad) and figure very prominently in sublime
wisdom.
Existence and Essence
Is existence substantive, or is essence? We always distinguish two valid senses in which
things may be spoken of: the isness of a thing and the whatness of a thing. For instance,
we know that man is, the tree is, number is, and quantity is, but number has one whatness,
one essence, and man has another. If we ask, "What is number?" we
receive one answer. If we ask, "What is man?" we receive another.
Many things have a patent isness; that is, we know that they are. But
we may not know what they are. For instance, we know that life is or that electricity is,
but we may not know what life is or what electricity is. We know what many things are-for
instance, we have a clear definition of a circle and so know what a circle is-but we do
not know whether the circle exists in objective nature. Thus, isness is something other
than whatness.
This plurality, this dichotomy of essence and existence, is purely
subjective. In extensional reality, no thing is twofold. Therefore, one of these two is
objectively so and substantive, and the other is nominal and not substantive.
The whole question of existentialism versus essentialism has no ancient
historical antecedents. This topic originated in the Islamic world. None of the early
philosophers, Farabi, Avicenna, Khwaja Nasir ad-Din Tusi, or even Suhravardi, discussed
anything under this heading. The topic made its debut in philosophy in the time of Mir
Damad (the beginning of the eleventh century of the Hijra. Mir Damad was an essentialist.
However, his famous pupil, Mulla Sadra, made a compelling case for existentialism, and
from then onward, every philosopher of note has been an existentialist. In the
third volume of UsuI-i Falsafa va Ravish-i Ri'azism, I have discussed the
respective ideas of the 'urafa', the mutakallimin, and the philosophers as
precursors to this philosophical conception of Mulla Sadra's.
Another philosophy sometimes known as existentialism has flourished in
our own time. This form of existentialism pertains to man and has reference to the idea
that man, by contrast with all other beings, has no definite, preassigned essence and no
form determined by nature. Man designs and builds his own whatness.
This idea is largely correct and supported by Islamic philosophy,
except that, what in Islamic philosophy is called existentialism does not apply to man
alone, but to the whole universe, and, second, when we speak of existentialism or isalat-I
vujud in an Islamic context, we are using the term isalat (-ism) in its sense
of substantive reality or objective being, as opposed to nominal or mental existence. When
we use it in the Western context of modern existentialism, we are using it in its sense of
primacy or priority. One should by no means conflate the two senses.
The Objective and the Subjective
A thing is either objective or subjective. Objective being means being external to and
independent of man's mind. We know, for instance, that mountain, sea, and plain have being
external to our minds and independent of them. Whether our minds conceive of them or not,
indeed, whether ourselves and our minds exist or not, mountain, sea, and plain exist.
But that mountain, sea, and plain have an existence in our minds as
well. When we imagine them, we give them being in our minds. The being things find in our
minds is called subjective being or mental being.
Two questions arise here. One is why the images of things appearing in
our minds should be conceived of as a kind o fbeing for those things in our minds. If they
are, one might say that the image of a thing painted on a wall or printed on a sheet of
paper deserves to be called another kind of being, a parietal being or a papyraceous
being. If we term mental images a form of being for the thing imagined, to be just, we
have employed a metaphor and not spoken the literal truth, but philosophy ought to deal
with the literal truth.
The relation of a mental form to an external object (for instance, the
relation of a mental mountain or sea to an external mountain or sea) is far more profound
than the relation of the picture of a mountain or a sea on a sheet of paper or a wall to
that external mountain or sea. If what appears in the mind were only a simple image, it
would never give rise to consciousness, just as the image on the wall does not give rise
to consciousness in the wall. Rather, the mental image is consciousness itself.
The other question is whether mental being, as a concept actually
relating to man and the human psyche, belongs to the realm of psychology. Philosophy deals
with general questions, and such particular questions pertain to the sciences.
Philosophers have demonstrated that we are conscious of external
objects because our mental images, far from being simple, area kind of realisation of
existence in our minds for the essences (mahiya) of the objects. Although from
one standpoint, the question of mental images is a question of the human psyche and so
belongs to the field of psychology, from another standpoint, that man's mind is in fact
another emergence (nash'a) of being, resulting in being in its essence taking two
forms, subjective and objective, it is a question for philosophy.
Avicenna and Mulla Sadra have said (the former allusively, near the
beginning of the "Ilahiyat" of his Shifa and the latter explicitly
and at length in his commentary to the same work) that at times a question may pertain to
two different disciplines from two standpoints; for instance, a question may pertain to
philosophy from one standpoint and to the natural sciences from another.
Truth and Error
The question of mental being bas another angle that has been studied: It has to do with
the validity of perceptions, the extent to which our perceptions, sensations, and
conceptions of the external world are valid. From ancient times, philosophers have asked
whether what we perceive of an object by means of our senses or our reason corresponds to
actuality, the thing in itself.
Some postulate that some of our sense perceptions or rational
perceptions do correspond to actuality, the thing in itself, and some do not. Those that
correspond to actuality are termed "truth," and those that do not are termed
"error." Sight, hearing, taste, touch, and smell are all subject to error. But
most of our sense perceptions correspond fully to reality. Through these same senses, we
accurately distinguish night from day, far from near, large from small in volume, tough
from smooth, and cold from hot.
Our reason is likewise subject to error. Logic was compiled to avert
errors of the reason in its deductions. But most of our rational deductions are valid.
When we add up all the debits and all the credits in a ledger and subtract the former from
the latter, we are performing a mental and rational procedure that we are perfectly
assured will hold true if we are sufficiently careful and exact.
However, the Sophists of Greece denied the distinction between truth
and error. They said that whatever some person feels and thinks is for that person the
truth. They said that man is the measure of all things. They radically denied reality and,
having denied it, left nothing in corresponding to which man's perceptions and sensations
could be true and in failing to correspond to which they could be erroneous.
The Sophists were contemporaries of Socrates
(Socrates came along near the close of the Sophist period). Protagoras and Gorgias are two
famous Sophists. Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle rebelled against them.
After Aristotle's time, another group appeared in Alexandria, called
the Sceptics, the most famous of whom is Pyrrho. The Skeptics did not deny actuality in
principle but denied that human perceptions correspond to it. They said that one perceives
an object in a certain way under the influence of internal states and certain external
conditions. Sometimes two people experiencing different states or viewing from different
angles will seethe same event in two different ways. A thing may appear ugly in one's eyes
and beautiful in another's, or single in one's eyes and double in another's. The air may
feel warm to one and cold to another. A flavor may taste sweet to one and bitter to
another. The Skeptics, like the Sophists, denied the validity of knowledge.
Bishop Berkeley wholly rejects external reality. No one has been able
to refute his reasons for his position, although everyone knows they are fallacious.
Those who have sought a reply to the ancient Sophists exemplifled by
Berkeley have not taken the approach that could resolve the sophism. The philosophers of
Islam have held that the basic approach to resolving this sophism consists in our
perceiving the reality of mental being. Only thus is the puzzle solved.
In approaching mental being, the hukama of Islam first define
knowledge, or perception, as consisting in a kind of being for the oblect perceived within
the being of the perceiver. They go on to cite certain demonstrations in support of this
position, and then they recount and reply to certain objections to mental being or
allegations of problems in it.
This topic did not exist in this form early in the Islamic period and afortiori
did not exist in Hellenic times. Nasir ad-Din Tusi was the first to speak of the
objective and the subjective in his works of philosophy and kalam. Thereafter, it
came to occupy a major place in the works of such comparatively recent philosophers as
Mulla Sadra and Mulla Hadi Sabzavari. Farabi, Avicenna, and even Suhravardi, as well as
their followers, never broached the subject of mental being or even used the term in their
works. The term first appeared after Avicenna's time.
However, what Farabi and Avicenna said on other subjects shows that
they believed perception to consist of a simulacrum of the reality of the object perceived
within the being of the perceiver. But they neither sought to demonstrate this point nor
conceived of it as an independent question of being, an independent division of being.
The Created in Time and the Eternal
The Arabic word hadith has the lexical and customary meaning of new, and qadim means
old. However, these words have other meanings in the terminologies of philosophy and kalam.
Like other people, when philosophers speak of the hadith and the qadim, they
seek to know what is new and what is old, but in speaking of a thing as new, they mean
that before it was, it was not-that is, that first it was not, then it was. In speaking
ofa thing as old, they mean that it always has been and never was not. Suppose there is a
tree that has lived for billions of years. In common usage, it would be spoken of as old,
quite old indeed, but according to the terminologies of philosophy and kalam, it is
hadith (new) because there was a time billions of years ago when it was not.
Philosophers define createdness in time (huduth) as the
precedence of a thing's nonbeing to its being, and they define eternality (qidam) as
the nonprecedence of a thing's nonbeing to its being. Therefore, an entity is created in
time whose nonbeing precedes its being, and an entity is eternal for which no nonbeing
prior to its being can be conceived.
Discussion of the question of the created in time and the eternal turns
on this point: Is everything in the universe created in time and nothing eternal, such
that whatever we consider first was not and then was? Or is everything eternal and nothing
created in time, such that everything has always been? Or are some things created in time,
and some eternal, such that, for instance, shapes, forms, and externals are created in
time, but matter, subjects, and invisible things are eternal? Or are individuals and parts
created in time, whereas species and wholes are eternal? Or are natural and material
phenomena created in time, whereas abstract and suprameterial phenomena are eternal? Or is
only God, the Creator of the whole and Cause of causes, eternal, whereas all else is
created in time? Overall, is the universe created in time, or is it eternal?
The mutakallimin of Islam believe that only God is eternal. All
else-matter and form, individuals and species, parts and wholes, abstract and
material-constitutes what is called the world or 'other' (masiva) and is created in time.
The philosophers of Islam, however, believe that createdness in time is a property of the
material world, whereas the supernatural worlds are abstract and eternal. In the world of
nature, too, principles and universals are eternal, whereas the phenomena and particulars
are created in time. Therefore, the universe is created in time with respect to its
phenomena and particulars but eternal with respect to its principles and universals.
Debate over createdness in time and eternality has excited acrimonious
disputes between the philosophers and the mutakallimin. Abu Hamid Ghazali, who,
although leaning to 'irfan and Sufism in most of his works, leans to kalam in
some, declares Avicenna an unbeliever for his stand on several questions, among them his
belief in the eternality of the world. In his famous Tahajut al-Falsafa (The
incoherence of the philosophers), Ghazali has criticised philosophers on twenty points and
exposed what he believed to be the incoherencies in their thought. Ibn Rushd of Andalusia
has rebutted Ghazali in Tahajut at- Tahafut (The incoherence of the
"incoherence").
The mutakallimin say that if a thing is not created in time but
eternal-if it has always been and never not been-then that thing has no need of a creator
and cause. Therefore, if we suppose other eternal things exist than the Essence of the
Truth, it follows that they will have no need of a creator and so in reality be necessary
beings in their essence, like God, and the demonstrations that show the Necessary Being in
Essence to be singular do not permit us to profess more than one such Necessary Being.
Accordingly, no more than one Eternal Being exists, and all else is created in time.
Therefore, the universe is created in time, including the abstract and the material,
principles and phenomena, species and individuals, wholes and parts, matter and form,
visible and invisible.
The philosophers have rebutted the arguments of the mutakallimin decisively,
saying that all the confusion turns on one point, which consists in supposing that, if a
thing has a continuous existence into the indefinite past, it has no need of a cause,
whereas this is not so. A thing's need or lack of need for a cause pertains to its
essence, which makes it a necessary being or a possible being; it has nothing to do with
its createdness in time or eternality. By analogy, the sun's radiance stems
from the sun and cannot exist apart from it. Its existence depends on the sun's existence.
It is the sun's luminance and issues from the sun whether we suppose there was a time this
radiance did not exist or we suppose it has always existed, along with the sun. If we
suppose that the sun's radiance has coexisted with the sun itself from preeternity to
posteternity, this does not entail its having no need of the sun.
The philosophers maintain that the relation of the universe to God is
as the relation of the radiance to the sun, with this difference: The sun is not conscious
of itself or of its action and does not perform its function as an act of will; the
contrary is true of God.
At times we encounter expressions in the primary texts of Islam that
compare the relation of the universe and God to the relation of radiance and the sun. The
noble verse of the Qur'an states, "God is the Light of the heavens and the
earth" (24:35). Exegetes have interpreted this verse to mean that God is the
light-giver of the heavens and the earth (that the being of heaven and earth is a ray of
God).
The philosophers do not adduce any evidence for the eternality of the
universe from the universe itself; rather, they approach this argument from the position
that God is the Absolutely Effulgent and the Eternally Beneficent-we cannot possibly
conceive of His effulgence (emanation) and beneficence as limited, as terminating
somewhere. In other words, the theistic philosophers have arrived at the eternality of the
universe through an a priori demonstration, that is, by making the being and attributes of
God the premise to the eternality of the universe.
Generally, those disbelieving in God advance the position of the
eternality of the universe, but the theistic philosophers say that the same thing
nonbelievers adduce as a reason for God's non-existence in their view implies God's
existence. The eternality of the universe is a hypothesis to nonbelievers, but it is an
established fact to theistic philosophers.
The Mutable and the Constant
Change means transformation and constancy means uniformity. We continually witness changes
in the universe. We ourselves continually make transitions from state to state, from
period to period, beginning when we are born and ending when we die. The same holds for
earth and sea, for mountains, trees, animals, stars, solar systems, and galaxies. Are
these changes outward, pertaining to the configuration, form, and accidents of the
universe, or are they profound and fundamental, such that no constant phenomenon exists in
the universe? Are the changes that occur in the universe transient and instantaneous, or
are they gradual and protracted?
These questions, too, date from remote times; they were discussed in
ancient Greece. Democritus, known as the father of the atomic theory and also as the
laughing philosopher, maintained that all change or transformation is superficial because
natural being is based on atomic particles, which are forever in one state and
unchangeable. The changes we witness are like those in a heap of gravel, massed sometimes
in one shape, sometimes in another, but never changing in identity or real nature. This is
the mechanistic outlook and constitutes a kind of mechanistic philosophy.
Another Greek philosopher, Heraclitus, maintains that nothing remains
in the same state for two successive instants. As he says, you cannot set foot twice in
the same river because at the second instant you are not who you were before and that
river is not the same river. This philosophy stands opposite to Democritus's in seeing
everything in a state of flux and inconstancy, but it says nothing contrary to mechanism;
that is, it advances no idea of dynamics.
Aristotle's philosophy has no quarrel with the idea that all the parts
of nature change, but undertakes to determine which changes are gradual and protracted and
which are transient and instantaneous. It terms the gradual changes "motion" and
the transient changes "generation and corruption" (that is' a transient coming
into being is called generation, and a transient extinction is called corruption). Because
Aristotle and his followers consider the basic changes occurring in this world, especially
those that appear in substances, as transient, they term this "the world of
generation and corruption."
At other moments, constancy obtains. If we regard changes as transient,
because they occur in an instant, although at other instants or through time things are
constant, such mutable things have a relative mutability and a relative constancy.
Therefore, if change is in the mode of motion, it is absolute change. If it is in the mode
of generation and corruption, if it is in an instantaneous mode-it is relative.
According to the Aristotelians, although nothing absolutely constant
and uniform exists in nature, but everything is mutable (contrary to the view of the
Democriteans), because substances are basic to nature and changes in substances are
transient, the world has a relative constancy along with relative change. But constancy
governs the world to a greater extent than does change.
Aristotle and the Aristotelians regard all things as falling under ten
basic generic classes, which they call the ten categories: substance, quantity, quality,
determination in space, position, determination in time, relation, condition, action, and
passion.
Motion occurs only in the categories of quantity, quality, and
determination in space. In all other categories change is transient; in other words, all
other categories enjoy a relative constancy. Even those three categories in which motion
occurs-because the motion is intermittent-are governed by a relative constancy. Therefore,
in Aristotle's philosophy, one encounters more constancy than change, more uniformity than
transformation.
Avicenna believed that motion occurs in the category of position as
well. He demonstrated that certain motions, such as the rotation of the earth about its
axis, constitute a positional motion, not a motion in spatial determination. Thus, after
Avicenna, motion in spatial determination was restricted to transferential motion.
Avicenna did not demonstrate the existence of a new sort of motion, but reclassified as
positional what had previously been categorised as a motion in spatial determination. His
reclassification is generally accepted.
Mulla Sadra effected a major transformation in Islamic philosophy by
demonstrating substantial motion. He demonstrated that, even on the basis of the
Aristotelian principles of matter and form, we must accept that the substances of the
world are in continuous motion; there is never so much as an instant of constancy and
uniformity in the substances of the world. The accidents (that is, the nine other
categories), as functions of the substances, are also in motion. According to Mulla Sadra,
nature equals motion, and motion equals continuous, uninterrupted creation and extinction.
Through the principle of substantial motion, the visage of the
Aristotelian universe is wholly transformed. According to this principle, nature, or
matter, equals motion. Time consists in the measure or tensile force of this substantial
motion, and constancy equals supernatural being. What exists consists of, on the one hand,
absolute change (nature) and, on the other, absolute constancy (the supernatural). The
constancy of nature is the constancy of order, not the constancy of being; that is, a
definite, immutable system governs the universe, and the contents of the system are all
mutable (they are change itself). Both the being and the system of this universe stem from
the supernal. Were it not for the governance of the other world, this world, which is
wholly flux and mutation, would be cut off from its past and future. "Many times has
the water exchanged in this stream,/Still the moon's and the stars' reflections
remain."
Prior to Mulla Sadra, the topic of the mutable and the constant was
felt to belong to the natural sciences, in that any determination or any division that
applies to a body qua body belongs to the natural sciences. It was said that it is
such-and-such a body that is either constant or mutable, or that is either still or in
motion. In other words, motion and stasis are among the accidents of a body. Therefore,
the topic of the constant and the mutable ought to fall wholly within the domain of the
natural sciences.
This all changed with Mulla Sadra's realisation of existentialism (the
substantive reality of being), his realisation of substantial motion, and his
demonstration that the natures of the universe constitute the mob ik qua mobile and the
mutable qua mutable (that is, that a body is not something to which motion is merely added
as an accident, whereby at times this motion can be annulled, leaving the motionless state
we call stasis). Rather, the natures of the universe are -motion itself, and the contrary
of this substantial motion is constancy, not stasis.
Stasis holds for the accidental motions the state of whose absence we
call stasis but is inconceivable in the case of essential, substantial motion. The
contrary of this substantial motion that is the substance itself consists of substances
for which constancy is the very essence. These are entities beyond space and time, devoid
of spatiotemporal forces, potentialities, or dimensions. Therefore, it is not the body
that is either constant or mutable. Rather, it is being qua being that appears
either as constancy itself (as supramaterial beings) or as continuous
flux/becoming/creation itself (the world of nature). Therefore, just as being is in its
essence divisible into necessary and possible, so is it in its essence divisible into the
constant and the fluid.
Thus, according to Mulla Sadra, only certain kinds of motions the
accidental motions of a body having stasis is for their opposite-ought to be studied under
the heading of the natural sciences. Other motions, or indeed these very motions when not
regarded from the standpoint of their being accidents of natural bodies, ought to be
discussed and studied in first philosophy. Mulla Sadra himself brought in his discussions
of motion under "general phenomena" in the Asfar in the course of
discussing potentials and acts, although it warranted a chapter to itself.
Among the key conclusions arising from this great
realisation-basically, that being in its essence is divisible into the constant and the
fluid and that constant being is one modality of being, while fluid being is another-is
that becoming is precisely a plane of being. Although, nominally speaking, we may regard
becoming as a synthesis of being and nonbeing, this synthesis is actually a kind of notion
or metaphor.
In truth it is the realisation of the substantive reality of being and
of the nominal status of essences (mahayat) that permits us to perceive this key
reality. Without a grasp of the substantive reality of being, neither a conception of
substantial motion nor a conception that flux and becoming are precisely a plane of being
would be possible.
Motion has recovered its proper place in the modern philosophy of
Europe by other avenues. Some philosophers came to believe that motion is the cornerstone
of nature, that nature equals becoming. However, because this idea was not based on
existentialism (the substantive reality of being) and the primary division of being into
the constant and the fluid, these philosophers supposed that becommg was the same union of
opposites that the ancients had deemed absurd. They likewise supposed that becoming
falsified the principle of identity (huhuya), which the ancients had taken for
granted.
These philosophers said that the presiding principle in the thought of
the ancients was the principle of constancy and that, in deeming beings constant, the
ancients had supposed that either being or nonbeing must hold sway over things. Therefore,
one alone of these holds true (the principle of the impossibility of union and
cancellation of opposites). That is, either there is always being or there is always
nonbeing; no third alternative obtains. Similarly, because the ancients thought things
constant, they supposed of everything that is itself (the principle of identity). But with
the realisation of the principle of motion and change in nature, the realisation that
nature is continually in a state of becoming, the two principles are groundless because
becoming is a union of being and nonbeing; where a thing is both being and non-being,
becoming has been demonstrated.
A thing in a state of becoming both is and is not; at every instant,
its self is its not-self; its selfs at once its self and not its self; the self of
its selfis progressively negated. Therefore, if the principle governing things were that
of being and nonbeing, both the principle of the impossibility of the union of opposites
and the principle of identity would hold true. Because the principle governing things is
the principle of becoming, neither of these other principles holds true.
The principle of the impossibility of the union of opposites and the
principle of identity, which held unrivalled sway over the minds of the ancients, arose
from a further principle that they also accepted implicitly: the principle of constancy.
As the natural sciences showed the invalidity of the principle of constancy, these two
principles, too, lost their credibility. This development represents the conception of
many modern philosophers, from Hegel onward.
Mulla Sadra invalidated the principle of constancy by other means.
Motion, according to his realisation, implies that nature equals inconstancy and constancy
equals abstraction. Unlike the modern philosophers, however, he never concludes that
because nature equals flux and becoming, the principle of the impossibility of the union
and cancellation of opposites is falsified. Although Mulla Sadra regards becoming as a
kind of union of being and nonbeing, he does not treat this as a union of opposites
because he has realized a more important principle: that being is divisible in its essence
into the constant and the fluid. Constant being is a plane of being, not a synthesis of
being and nonbeing. The synthesis of becoming from being and nonbeing is not a union of
two opposites just as it is not the negation of the self of a thing.
The modern philosophers' confusion has two roots: their failure to
perceive the division of being into the constant and the fluid and their inadequate
conception of the principles of contradiction and contrariety.
Cause and Effect
The most ancient of philosophical questions is that of cause and effect. The concept of
cause and effect appears in every philosophical system, unlike such concepts as
existentialism and subjective being, which have a prominent place in some philosophies and
pass unnoted in others, the concept of potential and act, which plays an important role in
Aristotelianism, or the concept of the constant and the mutable, which has a deservedly
prominent position in the philosophy of Mulla Sadra.
Causation is a kind of relation between two things, one of which we
call the cause and the other, the effect. This is the most profound of relations. The
relation of cause and effect consists in the cause's giving being to the effect. What the
effect realises from the cause is its whole being, its whole reality; therefore, if the
cause were not, the effect would not be. We find such a relation nowhere else. Therefore,
the effect's need of the cause is the keenest of needs, a need at the root of being.
Accordingly, if we would define cause, we must say, "A cause is that thing an effect
needs in its essence and being."
Every phenomenon is an effect, and every effect needs a cause;
therefore, every phenomenon needs a cause. That is, if a thing is not being itself in its
essence-if it has appeared as an accident, a phenomenon-it must have arisen through the
intervention of a factor we call a cause. Therefore, no phenomenon is without a cause. The
hypothesis contrary to this theory is that a phenomenon may appear without a cause. This
hypothesis is called coincidence (sudja) or chance (ittrfaq). The philosophy
of causality radically rejects this hypothesis.
Philosophers and mutakallimin concur that every phenomenon is an
effect and needs a cause, but the mutakallinun define such a phenomenon as created
in time (hadith), and the philosophers define it as possible (manikin). That
is, the mutakallimin say that whatever is created in time is an effect and needs a
cause, and the philosophers say that whatever is possible is an effect and needs a cause.
These two definitions lead to the different conclusions previously discussed in "The
Created in Time and the Eternal."
A certain cause produces only a certain effect, and a certain effect
proceeds only from a certain cause. There are special relations of dependence among the
beings of the universe such that any one thing cannot necessarily give rise to any other
thing and any one thing cannot necessarily arise from any other thing. We rely on this
truth in our everyday experience. For instance, eating is the cause of satiety, drinking
water is the cause of quenching of thirst, and study is the cause of literacy. Therefore,
if we wish to realise any of these qualities, we have resort to the appropriate cause. For
instance, we never drink water or study for the sake of satiety, nor do we consider eating
sufficient for the attainment of literacy.
Philosophy demonstrates that such a clear relation obtains among all
the processes in the universe. It makes this point through this definition: A unique
correspondence and symmetry govern every single cause-and-effect relation and appear in no
other such relation. This is the single most important principle in giving order to our
thought and in presenting the universe to our thought not as a chaotic aggregate in which
nothing is conditional upon anything else but as an ordered, systematic cosmos in which
every part has a special place, in which no one thing can displace another.
There are four kinds of cause in the philosophy of Aristotle: the
efficient cause, the final cause, the material cause, and the formal cause. These four
causes are well illustrated in human industry: If we build a house, the builder or workman
is the efficient cause; to dwell in that house is the final cause; the building materials
are the material cause; and the configuration of the house, in being appropriate to a
dwelling and not, say, to a granary, a bathhouse, or a mosque, is the formal cause. In
Aristotle's view, every natural phenomenon, whether a stone, a plant, or a human being,
has these same four causes.
Cause as defined by natural scientists differs somewhat from cause as
defined by theologians. In theology, or what we now call philosophy, cause means giver of
existence. Philosophers call what brings something into existence its cause. Otherwise
they do not call it cause, although they may at times call it contributory (mu 'idd). The
natural scientists, however, use the word "cause" even where the relation
between two things is simply one oftransfer of momentum. Therefore, in the natural
scientists' terminology, the builder is the cause of the house in being the point of issue
for its construction, through a series of transfers of materials. The theologians,
however, never call the builder the cause of the house, in that he does not bring the
house into being. Rather, the materials for the house existed beforehand, and the
builder's work has been confined to organizing them. Likewise, according to the natural
scientists, the relation of mother and father to child is causal; but according to
philosophy, it is that of an antecedent, a contributory factor, or a channel, not that of
a cause.
The sequence of causes (causes in the terminology of the philosophers,
not that of the natural scientists, that is, causes of being, not causes of motion)
terminates. It is absurd that it should be interminable. If the being of a thing proceeds
from a cause, arises from a cause, and if the being of that cause arises from a further
cause, and if the being of that cause arises from a yet further cause, this process could
go on through thousands, millions, billions of causes and more. However, it must finally
terminate in a cause that arises through its own essence and not through another cause.
Philosophers have often demonstrated that an endless regress of causes is absurd, which
phrase they shorten to a regress of causes is absurd or usually even further to regress is
absurd.
The word tasalsul (regress) is derived from the word silsila (sequence,
series, range), with the root meaning of chain. Therefore, tasalsul means an
endless chain of causes. Philosophers thus liken the ordered system of causes and effects
to a chain whose links interlock in sequence.
The Necessary, the Possible, and the Impossible
Logicians say that if we attribute a predicate to a subject, if, for instance, we say a is
b, the relation of 6 to a will have one of three qualities. First, it may be
necessary, that is, certain, inevitable, and inviolable; in other words, reason may refuse
to accept anything contrary to it. Second, the opposite may be true. That is, the relation
may be impossible, meaning it is absurd that the predicate should be an accident of the
subject. In other words, reason refuses to accept that it should be one.
Third, the relation may be such that it may be affirmed or negated;
that is, it is susceptible both to affirmation and to negation. In other words, reason
refuses to accept neither this relation nor its contrary.
For instance, if we consider the relation of the number four to
evenness, we see that it is necessary and certain. Reason refuses to accept its contrary.
Reason says that the number four is certainly and necessarily even. Therefore, necessity
governs this relation.
But if we say that the number five is even, this relation is
impossible. The number five has no possibility of being even, and our reason in perceiving
this relation rejects it. Therefore, impossibility and inconceivability govern this
relation.
But if we say that today the weather is sunny, this is a possible
relation. That is, the nature of the day does not require that the weather be sunny or
that it be cloudy. Either may accord with the nature of the day. Possibility governs this
relation.
It follows that, whatever subject and whatever predicate we consider,
their relation will not be devoid of these three qualities, which at times from a certain
standpoint we term the three modalities. I have described the logicians' approach.
The philosophers, who study being, say that any idea or concept we
consider, take as a subject, and predicate being of will fall under one of these three
categories. The relation of being to that idea or concept may be necessary; that is, that
thing must necessarily exist. We then call that thing a necessary being.
God is discussed in philosophy under the heading of proofs for
necessary being. Philosophical demonstrations show that there is a Being for which
nonexistence is absurd and existence is necessary.
If the relation of being to that idea is impossible, that is, if it is
absurd that it should exist, we call it an impossible being. An example is a body that is
at once spherical and cubical.
If the relation of being to that idea is possible, that is, if that
idea is an essence for which reason rejects neither the existence nor the nonexistence, we
call it a possible being. All the beings in the universe, in appearing and then
disappearing according to a sequence of causes, are possible beings.
Every possible being in itself becomes a necessary being through its
cause, but a being necessary through other, not a being necessary in itself. That is)
whenever all the causes and preconditions for a possible being exist, it must exist and so
becomes a being necessary through other. If it does not come into existence-if so much as
one of its preconditions or one of the elements of its causal nexus is lacking-it
becomes a being impossible through other.
The philosophers accordingly say that as long as a thing is not
necessary, it does not exist. That is, until the existence of a thing reaches the stage of
necessity, it will not come into being. Therefore, whatever comes into being does so
according to necessity, within a definite and inviolable system. Thus, the system
governing the universe and all that is in it is a necessary, certain, and inviolable
system. In the language of modern philosophers, it is a determinate system.
In discussing cause and effect, I said that the principle of
correspondence between cause and effect imparts a special order to our thought and marks
out a special connection between principles and ramifications, between causes and effects,
in our minds. This principle-that every possible being gains necessity from its
cause-which, from one standpoint, pertains to cause and effect and, from another, to
necessity and possibility, impans a special character to the system of our cosmology in
making it a necessary, certain, and inviolable system. Philosophy succinctly terms this
point the principle of cause-and effect necessity. If we accept the principle of the final
cause in reference to nature (if we accept that nature pursues ends in its evolutionary
journey and that all these ends revert to one primary end that is the end of ends), the
system of our cosmology takes on a further special character.